Epistemic Closure and Skepticism

نویسندگان

  • John A. BARKER
  • Fred ADAMS
  • John A. Barker
  • Fred Adams
چکیده

Closure is the epistemological thesis that if S knows that P and knows that P implies Q, then if S infers that Q, S knows that Q. Fred Dretske acknowledges that closure is plausible but contends that it should be rejected because it conflicts with the plausible thesis: Conclusive reasons (CR): S knows that P only if S believes P on the basis of conclusive reasons, i.e., reasons S wouldn’t have if it weren’t the case that P. Dretske develops an analysis of knowing that centers on CR, and argues that the requirement undermines skepticism by implying the falsity of closure. We develop a Dretske-style analysis of knowing that incorporates CR, and we argue that this analysis not only accords with closure, but also implies it. In addition, we argue that the analysis accounts for the prima facie plausibility of closure-invoking skeptical arguments, and nonetheless implies that they are fallacious. If our arguments turn out to be sound, the acceptability of Dretske’s analysis of knowing will be significantly enhanced by the fact that, despite implying closure, it undermines closure-based skepticism.

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

Epistemic closure, assumptions and topics of inquiry

According to the principle of epistemic closure, knowledge is closed under known implication. The principle is intuitive but it is problematic in some cases. Suppose you know you have hands and you know that ‘I have hands’ implies ‘I am not a brain-in-a-vat’. Does it follow that you know you are not a brain-in-a-vat? It seems not; it should not be so easy to refute skepticism. In this and simil...

متن کامل

Crimmins, Gonzales and Moore

Dretske, F. 1970. Epistemic operators. Journal of Philosophy 67: 1007–23. Dretske, F. 1981. The pragmatic dimension of knowledge. Philosophical Studies 40: 363–78. Lewis, D. 1979. Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8: 339–59. Lewis, D. 1996. Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 549–67. Stine, G. C. 1976. Skepticism, relevant alternatives, and de...

متن کامل

Arb There Counterexamples to the Cu)sure Principle? Arb Timrb Counterexamples to Tim Closure Principlb7

Very often, a person can't know a proposition without knowing various logical consequences of that proposition. So, for instance, if you know that your friend is wearing a yellow tie, you can't fail to know that your friend is wearing a tie. period. In this case, the relation of logical consequence is obvious. When the relation isn't obvious, a proposition you know may have a logical consequenc...

متن کامل

Epistemic Relativism

Epistemic relativism rejects the idea that claims can be assessed from a universally applicable, objective standpoint. It is greatly disdained because it suggests that the real ‘basis’ for our views is something fleeting, such as ‘‘the techniques of mass persuasion’’ (Thomas Kuhn 1970) or the determination of intellectuals to achieve ‘‘solidarity’’ (Rorty 1984) or ‘‘keep the conversation going’...

متن کامل

Skepticism, Sensitivity, and Closure, or Why the Closure Principle is Irrelevant to External World Skepticism

Is there a plausible argument for external world skepticism? Robert Nozick’s well–known discussion focuses upon arguments which utilize the Sensitivity Requirement and the Closure Principle. Nozick claims, correctly, that no such argument succeeds. But he gets almost all the details wrong. The Sensitivity Requirement and the Closure Principle are compatible; the Sensitivity Requirement is incor...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:

دوره   شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2010